Scientific Realism and the Study of Higher Education Curriculum and the Student Experience

Scientific Realism and the Study of Higher Education Curriculum and the Student Experience

Calvin Smith
Copyright: © 2017 |Pages: 19
DOI: 10.4018/978-1-5225-1738-2.ch008
OnDemand:
(Individual Chapters)
Available
$37.50
No Current Special Offers
TOTAL SAVINGS: $37.50

Abstract

This chapter elaborates and exemplifies the use of Structural Equation Modelling (SEM) in the analysis of the effects of curricula designs on student learning and experience in higher education. A brief didactic account of the origins of structural equation modelling is used to expose and explore fundamental assumptions, metaphysical and ontological commitments, and alternative views in the field. This is followed by an exemplification of the method by use of a case study of its application in studying a higher education curriculum design (work-integrated learning). The chapter argues for the adoption of a realist account of latent variables on the basis that the constructs they represent are in principle manipulable, even though experimental manipulation is not typically a feature of research on curricula in higher education.
Chapter Preview
Top

Philosophy Of Science

A Debated Issue

The existence of the current volume attests to the fact that in the social sciences in particular, but across all of the scientific enterprise, philosophical analysis of the logic of scientific inquiry, and the claims made about the methods and processes of science, has created considerable divisions, at least among those engaged in this debate, if not among the practitioners themselves.

The philosophical discourse on the logic, sociology, politics, ontology and epistemology of scientific inquiry is rich and engaged in earnestly. The debate ranges from Marx’s structuralism to Weber’s verstehen sociology, through Polanyi’s and Schutz’s phenomenological and ethnomethodological expositions, to Kuhn’s synthesis of “normal science” and “revolutions,” to Harding’s stand-point epistemologies and feminist critiques, to Feyerabend’s and Latour’s sincere and contrary skepticisms (Feyerabend, 2010; Hacking, 1981, 1992; Harding & Hintikka, 1983; Harding, 1986; Kuhn, 1962; Latour, 1986, 1999; Pickering, 1992; Polanyi, 1966; Schutz, 1962).

These debates have played out in many disciplines, but in the discipline of higher education the debate seems to be comparatively, and surprisingly, muted; the current volume addresses this gap in a direct and pragmatic way by linking “approach” or “method” to the range ontological, epistemological and metaphysical commitments that approaches imply. An account of the assumptions implicit in one approach to analyzing higher education students, in context, using quantitative data and methods is presented in this chapter.

These debates have various themes but four key themes in the philosophy of science are:

  • Objectivity: Is it possible to do science in a way that is defensibly or incontrovertibly based on unbiased measures and interpretations that are not influenced by the perceptual or theoretical preconceptions or political prejudices of the researchers?

  • Realism: Is there a real world that persists independently of and which is beyond instances of human perceptions of it?

  • Causality: Does it make sense and is it reasonable to assume, and is it possible to “see” or measure the causal mechanisms that are thought to operate between things in the world?

  • Latency: What is the ontological status of latent variables, i.e., theoretical constructs or ideas whose presence in the world is only known through one or more manifest measurable variables?

A tension persists, within the social sciences generally, as to the legitimacy of empiricist and positivist approaches to inquiry. As Sayer puts it:

At the centre of social science’s internal crisis have been attacks on orthodox conceptions usually termed ‘positivist’ or ‘empiricist’. So many different doctrines and practices have been identified with these terms that they have become devalued and highly ambiguous, or even purely pejorative. Those who want to continue using them increasingly find that they have to preface arguments with tiresome digressions on ‘the real meaning of positivism’ and these often generate more heat than what follows. (Sayer, 1992, p. 7)

This tension is not limited to social sciences. In the philosophy of science the debate remains unresolved, though some writers can be found who commit to this or that perspective, offering cogently argued defenses of their positions. However, for any one of these there is at least one other steadfastly defending some contrary view (for a review see Chakravartty, 2015). Such debate helps to refine our collective reasoning about the issues.

Complete Chapter List

Search this Book:
Reset